Interestingly, the grue paradox and the raven paradox are closely related; more on that later. The grue paradox makes a solid argument against induction. To even begin appreciating this argument, it makes sense to visit/revisit why induction is relevant to science.
So, I will be starting this essay there. From thereon, I will be touching upon some of the challenges that the philosophers of science have faced with induction over the years.
Following this, we will finally be arriving at the grue paradox. Once we have covered the grue paradox, I will be exploring a few paradoxical states of confirmation. Without any further ado, let us begin.
If you think about it, the entire business of science hinges upon the following process:
Step 1:Make empirical observations and measure/gather data about a phenomenon.
Step 2: Form a hypothesis about what causes the observed phenomenon.
Step 3: Repeat experiments that confirm the cause for the phenomenon, and use inductive logic to generalise the cause in the form of a scientific law to predict future occurrences of the phenomenon.
In short, science confirms a hypothesis using observations/measurements from experiments/real world and uses inductive logic to establish the hypothesis as a scientific law. This scientific law, then, predicts/describes this phenomenon in the future (or past/present).
The transition from hypothesis/theory to law is not a simple one though. I have covered this in detail in this essay. If you are interested, check it out. But for the purposes of this essay, this level of understanding of the relationship between induction and science should suffice.
The Philosophy of Science: Induction Does Not Really Exist
One of the biggest challenges of science is that we don’t know why it works the way it does. Every scientific law ever created is a model of how a phenomenon occurs. Scientists create such laws based on what they observed in the past using induction.
If this pattern changes, then the law would not hold anymore. So, the more confirming instances there are, the stronger our trust or belief in scientific laws becomes. However, if there is only one instance that contradicts a scientific law, then our belief in it gets shattered.
In essence, induction works, until it doesn’t! So, should we give up on it? Well, John Stuart Mill made a good case for induction by arguing that nature has regularities, and it is only by induction we know that it has regularities.
It is easy to note that this logic is circular; he knew this as well. But it kind of does the job and numerous contemporary philosophers such as Max Black agreed with him.
A German philosopher named Hans Reichenbach took this argument even further in what is now famous as a pragmatic justification of induction. He argued that if there is any way for us to guess what the unexamined parts of nature look like, it has to be by induction. In essence, he meant that if induction does not work, nothing else in science would work either.
Bertrand Russell and Rudolf Carnap seemed to agree with Reichenbach, although Russell did not find the argument satisfying enough. Carnap, on the other hand, tried to construct a probability-based inductive logic system from scratch in his work titled “Logical Foundations of Probability” (1950). Notable philosophers such as Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn thought that this approach was misguided though.
Then came Carl Gustav Hempel with his raven paradox. If you have read my essay on this paradox, you know how notorious it can be. Following this, an American philosopher named Nelson Goodman came up with the grue paradox in his book titled “Fact, Fiction, and Forecast”.
Many respectable philosophers and scientists of the time regarded this paradox to be equally notorious as the raven paradox. Now, it is our turn to experience what this paradox is all about.
The Grue Paradox Explained
We use the word “emerald” to describe a green gemstone; the colour is due to trace amounts of chromium or sometimes vanadium. Based on this, expressions such as “emerald green” have become commonplace.
Let us say that the law here is “all emeralds are green”. But one fine day, a prolific and established scientist comes along and claims that “all emeralds are grue.”
People don’t really understand what “grue” means. So, they demand an explanation from the famous scientist. This is the explanation he provides:
All emeralds will be green until 31.12.3022.
But from 01.12.3023 onwards, all emeralds will be blue.
To capture both the properties of all emeralds, I propose the predicate “grue” (green-blue).
Are emeralds green or blue — Illustrative art created by the author
If we are to entertain this scientist, every passing day that we observe “green” emeralds confirms this scientist’s hypothesis. So, it should increase our belief in this hypothesis.
But let’s be honest. Does it really? The answer is no. This is, in essence, the grue paradox. If this confirmation does not increase our trust or belief in the scientist’s hypothesis, why should any confirmation of any law gain our trust or belief? While you ponder upon that question, let me present you with more complications.
The Paradoxical Nature of Confirmations
It is clear that the grue paradox (as well as the raven paradox) deals with the notion of confirmation. One of the philosophical questions seems to be how and why does confirmation increase our trust or belief?
This discussion becomes more complicated when we consider the fact that under certain circumstances, confirmations can actually discredit or even falsify a hypothesis. Here is an example from Paul Berent:
6ft. vs. 99ft. (not to scale) — Illustrative art created by the author
Let us say that the basic hypothesis is, “All men are less than 100 feet tall”. All of a sudden, we discover a man who is 99 feet tall. While this observation should logically confirm the hypothesis, you and I both know that our confidence in the hypothesis would be significantly shaken.
Here is another one: suppose that we have ten cards whose values range from ace all the way up to 10. Now, I shuffle the cards and deal them face down in a row. Your hypothesis is “no card with value n is in the nth position from the left.”
To your amazement, you confirm your hypothesis 9 times in a row as you turn the first nine cards over. However, this should not increase your confidence in your hypothesis. If none of the turned cards is 10, then the tenth one has to be the 10, thus falsifying your hypothesis.
On a related note note, Richard K. Guy once wrote a hilarious yet ingenious paper titled “The Strong Law of Small Numbers”. I have covered this paper and its implications in this essay. If you are interested, check it out. Turning back to induction, where does all of this leave us?
The Grue Paradox: Induction Does Not Really Exist
Paradoxes like the grue paradox, the raven paradox, and the related family of confirmation-based veridical paradoxes help us come to terms with the following truth:
We don’t even have a qualitative understanding of inductive logic, let alone a quantitative one.
Outside of mathematics, the notion of induction loses its deterministic promise. However, it still works, and what’s worse, it’s the best we’ve got!
As we fumble around to make sense of our universe and nature, our challenges with induction might very well reflect the limitations of our very nature as human beings.
We use cookies on our website to give you the most relevant experience by remembering your preferences and repeat visits. By clicking “Accept”, you consent to the use of ALL the cookies.
This website uses cookies to improve your experience while you navigate through the website. Out of these, the cookies that are categorized as necessary are stored on your browser as they are essential for the working of basic functionalities of the website. We also use third-party cookies that help us analyze and understand how you use this website. These cookies will be stored in your browser only with your consent. You also have the option to opt-out of these cookies. But opting out of some of these cookies may affect your browsing experience.
Necessary cookies are absolutely essential for the website to function properly. These cookies ensure basic functionalities and security features of the website, anonymously.
Cookie
Duration
Description
cookielawinfo-checkbox-advertisement
1 year
Set by the GDPR Cookie Consent plugin, this cookie is used to record the user consent for the cookies in the "Advertisement" category .
cookielawinfo-checkbox-analytics
11 months
This cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Analytics".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-functional
11 months
The cookie is set by GDPR cookie consent to record the user consent for the cookies in the category "Functional".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-necessary
11 months
This cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookies is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Necessary".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-others
11 months
This cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Other.
cookielawinfo-checkbox-performance
11 months
This cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Performance".
CookieLawInfoConsent
1 year
Records the default button state of the corresponding category & the status of CCPA. It works only in coordination with the primary cookie.
viewed_cookie_policy
11 months
The cookie is set by the GDPR Cookie Consent plugin and is used to store whether or not user has consented to the use of cookies. It does not store any personal data.
Functional cookies help to perform certain functionalities like sharing the content of the website on social media platforms, collect feedbacks, and other third-party features.
Performance cookies are used to understand and analyze the key performance indexes of the website which helps in delivering a better user experience for the visitors.
Cookie
Duration
Description
_gat
1 minute
This cookie is installed by Google Universal Analytics to restrain request rate and thus limit the collection of data on high traffic sites.
Analytical cookies are used to understand how visitors interact with the website. These cookies help provide information on metrics the number of visitors, bounce rate, traffic source, etc.
Cookie
Duration
Description
__gads
1 year 24 days
The __gads cookie, set by Google, is stored under DoubleClick domain and tracks the number of times users see an advert, measures the success of the campaign and calculates its revenue. This cookie can only be read from the domain they are set on and will not track any data while browsing through other sites.
_ga
2 years
The _ga cookie, installed by Google Analytics, calculates visitor, session and campaign data and also keeps track of site usage for the site's analytics report. The cookie stores information anonymously and assigns a randomly generated number to recognize unique visitors.
_ga_R5WSNS3HKS
2 years
This cookie is installed by Google Analytics.
_gat_gtag_UA_131795354_1
1 minute
Set by Google to distinguish users.
_gid
1 day
Installed by Google Analytics, _gid cookie stores information on how visitors use a website, while also creating an analytics report of the website's performance. Some of the data that are collected include the number of visitors, their source, and the pages they visit anonymously.
CONSENT
2 years
YouTube sets this cookie via embedded youtube-videos and registers anonymous statistical data.
Advertisement cookies are used to provide visitors with relevant ads and marketing campaigns. These cookies track visitors across websites and collect information to provide customized ads.
Cookie
Duration
Description
IDE
1 year 24 days
Google DoubleClick IDE cookies are used to store information about how the user uses the website to present them with relevant ads and according to the user profile.
test_cookie
15 minutes
The test_cookie is set by doubleclick.net and is used to determine if the user's browser supports cookies.
VISITOR_INFO1_LIVE
5 months 27 days
A cookie set by YouTube to measure bandwidth that determines whether the user gets the new or old player interface.
YSC
session
YSC cookie is set by Youtube and is used to track the views of embedded videos on Youtube pages.
yt-remote-connected-devices
never
YouTube sets this cookie to store the video preferences of the user using embedded YouTube video.
yt-remote-device-id
never
YouTube sets this cookie to store the video preferences of the user using embedded YouTube video.
Comments