In my previous essay on the raven paradox, I covered how the paradox occurs. It all started with the playful-sounding logic puzzle that logician and philosopher Carl Gustav Hempel formulated in the 1940s. He starts with the statement:
āAll ravens are black.ā
Given this statement, on the one hand, we consider the sighting of a black raven intuitively as evidence confirming the statement. On the other hand, we do not consider the sighting of a green apple intuitively as evidence confirming the original statement. However, the real challenge occurs when our scientific logic system does consider the sighting of a green apple as confirmational evidence as well.
We essentially apply the plausible concepts of āinstance confirmationā, equivalence condition, and contrapositive statement to arrive at an implausible-looking conclusion. This is the paradox ā it reveals a contradiction between intuition and inductive reasoning. For more details, please check out my original essay on this topic.
In this essay, I will be covering how one could choose to tackle this paradox. To begin, let us analyse the fundamental question underlying the challenge.
In all its complexity and minutiae, the raven paradox is asking a very fundamental question:
What is āevidenceā?
It reveals to us our own inadequate definition of the word āevidenceā. If we are somehow able to come to an agreement on what this word means, we would be able to tackle this paradox.
But alas! Some of the deepest challenges arise from the simplest of questions. The scientific community and deep thinkers alike have been at odds over the meaning of the word āevidenceā over the past decades.
We will take a look at some of the most prominent approaches people have taken to tackle the raven paradox so far. Before we proceed, know that any attempt to tackle the paradox must also give a unique and consistent explanation as to why the paradox occurs.
Acceptance of the Raven Paradox
Proponents of the āacceptanceā approach choose to merely accept non-ravens as relevant evidence of the original statement. Hempel himself chose this approach to tackle the paradox. He argued that the result looks paradoxical only because we have prior knowledge like in the case of the raven example.
To explain his point further, consider the following statement:
āAll sodium salts burn yellow.ā
Its contrapositive statement is as follows:
āWhatever does not burn yellow is not a sodium salt.ā
Now imagine a situation where you observe someone holding a colourless cube of some unknown material in a flame. You notice that the cube does not burn.
Based on this, you consider this as evidence that this material is not a sodium salt. Later on, the person holding the cube reveals to you that the substance is ice (made of water).
Had you known that it was ice all along, you might not have considered the event of it not burning as evidence of the original statement (or its contrapositive).
In short, supporters of this line of thought argue that the notion of evidence should be separated from prior knowledge. Evidence should be considered unbiased from what we already know or do not know. In Henpelās own words:
āIf we assume this additional information as given (that the substance is ice), then, of course, the outcome of the experiment can add no strength to the hypothesis under consideration. But if we are careful to avoid this tacit reference to additional knowledge ā¦ the paradoxes vanish.ā
– Carl Gustav Hempel
The Bayesian Approach to the Raven Paradox
The Bayesian faction of scientists and deep thinkers argues that prior knowledge should not be ignored and that evidence should be built on top of what we already know. Based on Bayesian probability, this approach naturally considers each instance of an event in relation to the total number of possible occurrences.
For instance, when you observe a black raven, you should also consider the total number of all ravens. That is likely a very large number, but still doable. However, when we consider the contrapositive condition, things change.
In the event that you observe a green apple, you should also consider the total number of all non-black entities. This is likely a significantly larger number than the total number of ravens.
This approach argues that the paradox occurs because we intuitively estimate the amount of evidence provided by the sighting of a green apple to be zero. In reality, it is likely non-zero but infinitesimally small.
At this point, we arrive at another challenge! The Bayesian faction is sub-divided into two more groups (human beings are truly special). One group argues for what we have just seen so far: the sighting of a black raven provides more evidence than the sighting of a green apple.
The other group argues that based on logical equivalence, both events must symmetrically provide the same amount of evidence, in that, they both reduce the entropy by the same amount.
We havenāt even started considering time dependencies. For example, when I say that you should consider all ravens, does this include all the ravens of the past, the present, and the future? How are you supposed to know how future ravens would look? As you see, things get really complicated really fast.
Where Do We Go from Here?
Even today, the debate between the various approaches to tackle the raven paradox is still ongoing. I have just scratched the surface of the scientific discussion with this essay. There are other nuanced approaches that I havenāt even covered here (I just covered the most prominent ones).
At its core, the debate circles around two questions:
1. What is āevidenceā?
2. How do we handle prior knowledge when treating evidence?
As human beings, we seem to be divided on answers to these questions. Hereās my challenge: every argument sounds convincing until you read or consider the other one. A part of me wants to accept them all; just not all at once.
I meditate often upon this topic. Over the years, I have come to believe that it might very well be impossible to arrive at a single āsolutionā for this paradox. The way we tackle this paradox remains very context-dependent.
Depending upon the requirements and boundary conditions we have, one approach may be more fruitful than the other. In situations where it makes sense to include and weigh prior knowledge, the Bayesian approach makes sense. On the other hand, when gauging events with independent probabilities, it makes sense to take the acceptance approach from Hempel and co.
Things get even more complicated when we start considering advanced phenomena such as ergodicity (a topic for another day). In short, my approach to tackling the raven paradox is: “it depends!“
We use cookies on our website to give you the most relevant experience by remembering your preferences and repeat visits. By clicking āAcceptā, you consent to the use of ALL the cookies.
This website uses cookies to improve your experience while you navigate through the website. Out of these, the cookies that are categorized as necessary are stored on your browser as they are essential for the working of basic functionalities of the website. We also use third-party cookies that help us analyze and understand how you use this website. These cookies will be stored in your browser only with your consent. You also have the option to opt-out of these cookies. But opting out of some of these cookies may affect your browsing experience.
Necessary cookies are absolutely essential for the website to function properly. These cookies ensure basic functionalities and security features of the website, anonymously.
Cookie
Duration
Description
cookielawinfo-checkbox-advertisement
1 year
Set by the GDPR Cookie Consent plugin, this cookie is used to record the user consent for the cookies in the "Advertisement" category .
cookielawinfo-checkbox-analytics
11 months
This cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Analytics".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-functional
11 months
The cookie is set by GDPR cookie consent to record the user consent for the cookies in the category "Functional".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-necessary
11 months
This cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookies is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Necessary".
cookielawinfo-checkbox-others
11 months
This cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Other.
cookielawinfo-checkbox-performance
11 months
This cookie is set by GDPR Cookie Consent plugin. The cookie is used to store the user consent for the cookies in the category "Performance".
CookieLawInfoConsent
1 year
Records the default button state of the corresponding category & the status of CCPA. It works only in coordination with the primary cookie.
viewed_cookie_policy
11 months
The cookie is set by the GDPR Cookie Consent plugin and is used to store whether or not user has consented to the use of cookies. It does not store any personal data.
Functional cookies help to perform certain functionalities like sharing the content of the website on social media platforms, collect feedbacks, and other third-party features.
Performance cookies are used to understand and analyze the key performance indexes of the website which helps in delivering a better user experience for the visitors.
Cookie
Duration
Description
_gat
1 minute
This cookie is installed by Google Universal Analytics to restrain request rate and thus limit the collection of data on high traffic sites.
Analytical cookies are used to understand how visitors interact with the website. These cookies help provide information on metrics the number of visitors, bounce rate, traffic source, etc.
Cookie
Duration
Description
__gads
1 year 24 days
The __gads cookie, set by Google, is stored under DoubleClick domain and tracks the number of times users see an advert, measures the success of the campaign and calculates its revenue. This cookie can only be read from the domain they are set on and will not track any data while browsing through other sites.
_ga
2 years
The _ga cookie, installed by Google Analytics, calculates visitor, session and campaign data and also keeps track of site usage for the site's analytics report. The cookie stores information anonymously and assigns a randomly generated number to recognize unique visitors.
_ga_R5WSNS3HKS
2 years
This cookie is installed by Google Analytics.
_gat_gtag_UA_131795354_1
1 minute
Set by Google to distinguish users.
_gid
1 day
Installed by Google Analytics, _gid cookie stores information on how visitors use a website, while also creating an analytics report of the website's performance. Some of the data that are collected include the number of visitors, their source, and the pages they visit anonymously.
CONSENT
2 years
YouTube sets this cookie via embedded youtube-videos and registers anonymous statistical data.
Advertisement cookies are used to provide visitors with relevant ads and marketing campaigns. These cookies track visitors across websites and collect information to provide customized ads.
Cookie
Duration
Description
IDE
1 year 24 days
Google DoubleClick IDE cookies are used to store information about how the user uses the website to present them with relevant ads and according to the user profile.
test_cookie
15 minutes
The test_cookie is set by doubleclick.net and is used to determine if the user's browser supports cookies.
VISITOR_INFO1_LIVE
5 months 27 days
A cookie set by YouTube to measure bandwidth that determines whether the user gets the new or old player interface.
YSC
session
YSC cookie is set by Youtube and is used to track the views of embedded videos on Youtube pages.
yt-remote-connected-devices
never
YouTube sets this cookie to store the video preferences of the user using embedded YouTube video.
yt-remote-device-id
never
YouTube sets this cookie to store the video preferences of the user using embedded YouTube video.
Comments